fbpx

The Institution Formerly Known as Marriage

The Iowa court’s recent decision does not simply broaden marriage, it radically changes its nature. While marriage previously served public purposes of attaching mothers and fathers to their children and one another, now marriage merely serves as affirmation of adult feelings.

(This editorial first appeared on the website of the Witherspoon Institute, Public Discourse, Ethics, Law and the Common Good)

The Iowa court’s recent decision does not simply broaden marriage, it radically changes its nature. While marriage previously served public purposes
of attaching mothers and fathers to their children and one another, now marriage merely serves as affirmation of adult feelings.

The Iowa Supreme Court recently proved that the critics of same-sex “marriage” are correct: we are not being urged to make marriage more inclusive,
but to radically redefine the nature of marriage itself. With its decision, the Iowa Supreme Court covertly but profoundly changed the meaning
of marriage. The Court abolished the essential public purpose of marriage, and replaced it with a new understanding of marriage that is neither
essential nor public. The Institution Formerly Known as Marriage will be an empty shell in Iowa. As the movement to redefine marriage spreads across
the country, citizens should look to Iowa to see what this actually entails.

The essential purpose of marriage is to attach mothers and fathers to their children and to one another. Absent this purpose, we would not need marriage
as a distinct social institution. Human beings are not born as rational autonomous actors, they are the immature products of sexual relations between
a man and a woman, and they need the assistance of adults to survive. Marriage exists, in all times and places, to solve this social problem. If
our offspring were born as adults, ready to live independently, or if we reproduced through some form of asexual process, we would not need anything
like marriage.

Marriage also has a profoundly social purpose. Marriage creates its own small society consisting of mother, father, and children. That small social
unit contributes to the larger society by creating a functioning future—the next generation. Everyone benefits from having a next generation
that can sustain the society and keep its institutions going. Even when I personally am old, and even if I have not had any children myself, I
benefit from the fact that younger people are building cars and houses, providing medical and legal care, starting new businesses, and running
old ones. In modern developed countries, the family also saves the state a lot of money by taking care of its own dependent young, rather than
foisting that responsibility onto the taxpayers. Thus, the benefits of marriage go far beyond the benefits to the individual members of the family.

So, what did the Iowa Supreme Court have to say about the purposes of marriage? Did they view the requirement that marriage be between a man and a
woman as a violation of the principle of equal protection? Indeed. As the Court argued, “Equal protection demands that laws treat alike all people
who are ‘similarly situated with respect to the legitimate purposes of the law.’” If the Court can convince itself that the dual gender requirement
bears no relationship to the State’s purpose in having a marriage statute in the first place, then that requirement violates the Equal Protection
clause of the Iowa Constitution.

It should be evident that if the purpose of marriage is to attach mothers and fathers to their children and to one another, then the dual gender requirement
is perfectly permissible. Same-sex couples and opposite-sex couples are not the same with respect to this purpose. The Court had to come up with
a very limited understanding of the purposes of marriage in order to maintain that opposite-sex and same-sex couples are in fact similarly situated.

The Court enumerated several purposes directly. Marriage provides an institutional basis for defining relational rights and responsibilities; marriage
allows people to pool their resources; marriage recognizes people’s commitments; marriage provides comfort and happiness; marriage is a status,
not a contract.

But these reasons do not explain why we need marriage in particular. I have a relationship with my next-door neighbor. My family pools resources with
other members of a boat club. I have commitments to my employees and business associates. A pet brings me comfort and happiness. We do not need
the unique relationship called marriage for any of these purposes.

The Court alluded to several other possible purposes, without including them within its list of state purposes. “Therefore, with respect to the subject
and the purposes of Iowa’s marriage laws, we find that the plaintiffs are similarly situated compared to heterosexual persons. Plaintiffs are in
committed and loving relationships, many raising families, just like heterosexual couples. Moreover, official recognition of their status provides
an institutional basis for defining their fundamental relational rights and responsibilities, just as it does for heterosexual couples.”

The Court does not seem to realize that if these purposes really exhaust the list of legitimate state purposes of marriage, then there is no reason
to have marriage as a distinct legal structure in the first place. Moreover, these are all private purposes, not public purposes, of marriage.

The same-sex couples before the Court claim to be committed and to love each other. Why do we need marriage for that? I’m committed to my sister. I
love my best friend. Are we second class citizens because we are not married to each other? There is no state purpose whatsoever to be served by
my having some legal statement or affirmation attached to my love for my sister. Besides, who really wants the Court, or the state or anyone else
saying that our love is important to the state? People’s feelings are none of the state’s business.

The Court seems to understand this, for it gently and subtly elides the key issue of marriage law when it goes on to say: “Society benefits, for example,
from providing same-sex couples a stable framework within which to raise their children . . . just as it does when that framework is provided for
opposite-sex couples.” But wait a minute: How in the world does a same-sex couple obtain a child that is “theirs?”

This is precisely the way in which same-sex couples differ from opposite-sex couples. No child is born from a homosexual union. A child born to one
of them has another parent who has been quietly escorted into the lab or the backdoor, to make the conception possible. That person is quickly
escorted right back out the door, before he can claim any parental rights, or the child can claim any relational rights. Some of us believe that
these two people, the child and the opposite-sex parent, require and deserve some protection. But the Court of Iowa does not think them even worth
mentioning.

The social purpose of marriage has always been to attach mothers and fathers to their children, and to each other. This universal social purpose does
not even make it onto the Iowa Court’s short list. The reason should be obvious: opposite-sex couples and same-sex couples are not similarly situated
with respect to that purpose of marriage. If the Court found that attaching children to their parents and parents to one another is a purpose of
marriage, they would be unable to sustain their claim that man woman marriage violates the principle of equal protection under the law.

Society needs marriage because children have rights to care from their parents, rights which they can not defend on their own. Societies create marriage
to pro-actively protect the legitimate entitlements of children, and to provide for the future of the society. According to the Supreme Court of
Iowa, these provisions for children are no longer the purpose of marriage. We are left to guess as to how this truly essential public function
will be performed, now that the Court has surreptitiously removed it from the list of marriage’s jobs.

Iowa is a relatively homogeneous and prosperous state. This newly created lacuna in the purposes of the law may not harm Iowa much at first. But other
states have more diversity of opinion and practice about socially acceptable behavior, as well as greater economic and social stresses on married
life and child rearing. In those states, the cost of redefining marriage is likely to be more pronounced and immediate.

In sum, the Court has elevated the private, inessential purposes of marriage to the highest point in the hierarchy of values of marriage. Given this
new understanding, neither the longevity of marriage, nor fidelity within marriage can remain as important values. By the time the opponents of
conjugal marriage are finished with their redefinitions, marriage will be little more than a five-year renewable-term contract. The Institution
Formerly Known as Marriage will be nothing but a couple of individuals, loosely stapled together by the state.

Advocates of natural marriage, as opposed to genderless marriage, believe that society needs marriage to be a child-centered, gender-based social institution.
We have been arguing all along that same-sex “marriage” will be a gender-neutral institution, in which children are only a peripheral concern.
When the Supreme Court of Iowa established same-sex “marriage” by judicial decree, they proved our point for us.

 

Jennifer Roback Morse, Ph.D., is the Founder and President of the Ruth Institute

share with your friends:

Facebook
Twitter
YouTube

Want to dig in? Here’s more

Society needs these truths. Help us!